By Joseph Caulfield
Rage – Goddess, sing the rage of Peleus’ son Achilles,
murderous, doomed, that cost the Achaeans countless losses,
hurling down to the House of Death so many sturdy souls,
great fighters’ souls, but made their bodies carrion,
feasts for the dogs and birds and the will of Zeus was moving toward its end. Begin, Muse, when the two first broke and clashed,Agamemnon lord of men and brilliant Achilles….1
The Uniqueness of Family Law Litigation
Family law litigation leads to more burnout of the judges,
marital masters, lawyers, guardians ad litem, and mental health
workers than perhaps any other area of our practice. I t overloads
us, places an inordinate amount of pressure on us, frustrates us,
and has the capacity to taint our view of the world. U nwilling to
back down from the challenges, we are compelled to take on every
stressor that comes our way.2
Most judges who are murdered by dissatisfied parties are killed
by the irate domestic litigants, not by the criminal defendants.
The reason is simple: more emotional issues are involved than in
any other litigation.3 With such statistics, one wonders why N ew
Hampshire spends the manpower and time to so thoroughly search
the lawyers as they enter the courthouse, other than through some
strained sense of egalitarianism. Surely, we are a statistically innocuous
group.
In most areas of the law the roles of the parties are clear and
the opportunity for litigation fairly limited, as, for example, motor
vehicle personal injury law. S eldom have the two drivers met before
and, when the case is either tried or settled, seldom will they meet
again. They never loved each other, so if they hate each other now, as opposed to merely consider each other damned fools, the hate
is not a deep hate and abates readily when the case is concluded.
In criminal law, again the issues are clear-cut. I t is the government
against the individual. A criminal defendant may develop
hatred of a particular prosecutor and vice versa, but seldom does
a criminal defendant “hate” the government and, of course, the
government has no feelings, being too often the implacable W heel
of Karma. N either of the parties ever loved each other. A gain, the
encounter is limited and, although with certain defendants there
may be frequent additional encounters, the issues defining each
encounter are very different.
Family law litigation and probate litigation offer unique challenges.
Whenever a client comes to a lawyer with a horror story of
litigation that never ended, it is likely to involve a contested divorce
or a contested estate. Family law litigation and probate litigation
share the same weighty psychological issues, and these issues
drive the litigation, not the legal issues. I n a contested estate, the
litigants, in the guise of disputing the division of estate assets, are
often struggling over issues of “mother loved you best,” “I loved
mother best,” and, “if only you had taken better care of mother,
she’d be here today.” S ince the parties are not really struggling
about money, they seldom perform cost-benefit analyses, and
legal fees often escalate uncontrollably, producing little tangible
value. N ote, I wrote that the fees often escalate uncontrollably,
not that the parties pay these fees. T he parties have a lifetime of
grievances against each other and can take years to work them
out in the court system, if ever.
In family law litigation, the parties, again, have a long history
together, though, perhaps, not as long as in probate litigation.
The parties once loved each other romantically and lived together.
Now, often as conflicted co-parents, they hate each other. T hey
will sincerely confess to the court that the spouse, whom they once
held above all others, is not fit to have one unsupervised moment
of contact with their child, lest the child suffers some heinous fate.
Again, since the litigation is seldom about finances, despite what
the parties contend, legal fees are really no object, and the case cango on, and on, and on. Worse even than probate litigation, is family
law litigation, because most estates close in a couple of years no
matter how litigious the parties are. A divorce which occurs early
in the children’s life can go on through the children’s majority.
A while back, I was involved in a sad case involving two parents
who acrimoniously litigated the issue of custody of a special-needs
child through most of the child’s minority. U ndaunted by the
child attaining his majority, they continued litigation through
the vehicle of a contested guardianship.
Further, not content with trying to destroy the spouse, such
litigants, more frequently of late, then try to destroy the professionals
involved in the case, filing specious complaints with the
Judicial Conduct Committee, the Professional Conduct Committee
and the Guardian ad L item Board.
And, consider how children fare in these litigation disasters.
Although a parent within a violent family may think they are
protecting their children from this violence, 80 percent to 90
percent of these children report the opposite. I n fact, one out of
four times that a father murders a mother, their child is a witness.4
Even the most carefully crafted and intricately structured parenting
plan is not foolproof. As the saying goes, nothing is foolproof
because fools are so ingenious. Any family law practitioner with
some wake behind his or her keel will relate the often recurring,
malicious tricks. M other sends son to father’s barbecue with the
grandparents with son dressed in rags. Father returns daughter to
mother from the skiing trip keeping all the expensive new clothing.
Mother complains that whatever daughter eats at father’s makes
her sick/brings out her allergies/keeps her awake at night/makes
her sleepy during the day. Father complains that the video that
daughter watched at mother’s house was too old/too young/too
frightening/too boring. O f course, all too soon the children will
be telling the parents when and for how long they’ll be in the
company of each parent, on any given day, leading a more astute
parent to consider that the $50,000 she paid her attorney to obtain
this parenting schedule and no other, could have been better spent
on the child’s post-secondary education at best, or on visiting the
Isle of Capri, at worst.
However, to dismiss these family law disasters by assuming that
one or both of the parties have become crazed or angered beyond
reason misses an opportunity to comprehend how our understanding
of anger has changed, and what can be done to help.
Homer’s Iliad
The primary myth of our western culture, Homer’s Iliad,
was a family law disaster of nine years’ duration. Although long
before the French troubadours invented romantic love, consider
what Homer recounted for us. Helen, the wife of King Menelaus
of Sparta, eloped with Paris, the son of King Priam of Troy, about
1260 B CE. T o avenge this insult and to bring Helen home, the
Greeks launched an expeditionary fleet of 1,000 ships against
Troy. Agamemnon, the King of Mycenae, and Menelaus’ brotherin-law, was elected commander in chief.
Unfortunately, he was greedy, ambitious and arrogantly stupid. O ne of the Greeks who
accompanied Agamemnon was Achilles, who, in the judgment of
his peers, was more qualified than Agamemnon to command the
fleet. T he struggle between Agamemnon and Achilles is brought
to a climax nine years into the siege when Agamemnon publicly
humiliates Achilles by taking from him the beautiful Briseis, a
war prize with whom Achilles fell very much in love. T hereupon,
Achilles refuses to fight any longer for the Greeks and sulks in his
tent. Eventually Achilles learns compassion and experiences moral
growth. T his is brought about through the intersession of the Gods,
the death of Achilles’ male lover, Patroclus, at the hands of Hector,
Achilles’ slaying of Hector and desecration of his corpse, and
his personal encounter with King Priam. T hen, in fulfillment of
prophecy, Achilles is struck down by the cowardly arrow of P aris.5
This would be a “Greek tragedy” (tragoidia), but for the fact that
Greek tragedy, just as romantic love, had not yet been invented
(Subsequently developed in the theaters of Athens by Aeschylus,
Sophocles, and Euripides in the fifth century B CE.)
The I liad does not begin with an infringement of a moral code:
it begins with passions that are far more profound than moral rules
and are beyond the scope of reason, with forces operating in human
life which seem beyond human control. M orals have nothing to
do with it. Rage, “ménis,” is the ultimate sanction against taboo
behavior. Only Gods and heroes have “ménis.” A powerful and effective sanction, despite its outbreak in disorder, “ménis” keeps
the world in order and the cosmic categories intact.6
That it is Athena who initially advises Achilles to control his
rage is very telling. Although associated with war and battle,
the goddess Athena is described by the god Aries in the Iliad as
“aphrón,” crazed or frantic. However, it was more typical of
Athena to act with restraint even in battle, and she was more likely
to reveal herself in situations that demanded clear thinking, the
calming of emotions, and the restraint of violence. U nlike A ries,
she does not fight and seek out battle for the thrill of it, nor does
she express herself most fully in the bloodlust and tumult of battle
and killing, as does Aries.
For her, warfare is primarily political, tactical and expedient
– one way among others to obtain some goal or to protect some
cherished value. S he is more interested in martial arts techniques,
the skillful use of weapons, and the strategy of war, or the use of
cunning and reason, than she is in the din and frenzy of violent
struggle. Her presence in battle does not incite rage and fury;
her presence incites courage and daring, tempered with control
of the passions that can make a person reckless and vulnerable.
Therefore, it is only fitting that when Achilles first feels rage rising
within himself and reaches for his sword, intent upon slaying
Agamemnon, it is Athena who appears to him, grabbing him by
his hair. Achilles turns towards her and stares into her terrible
shining eyes. S he is not there to incite him to violence, however.
On the contrary, she has appeared to stay his hand. S he counsels
him to return Agamemnon’s insults with words of his own, but
to resist his urge to violence. I n return for his restraint, A thena
promises him greater rewards in the future.
In all her tales, Athena demonstrates a tendency to employ
wisdom, knowledge and cunning in leading events in the direction
she favors. Her way of achieving success is to employ reason,
intelligence and skill. O ne of Athena’s most common descriptions
is “bright eyed” (glaukopis) relating to her intelligence. T hat
she is associated with the owl, whose large luminous eyes are so
striking, also might be understood as suggesting her intelligent
nature. A consistent theme in the mythology and cult of Athena is
her identification with the city state of A thens where the tale is told
that, in the trial of Orestes for the murder of his mother Clytemnestra,
Athena established a court of justice in which democratic
voting by leading citizens decided the fate of the accused, thereby
doing away with the archaic and disruptive law of blood revenge.
However, it must never be forgotten that Athena wields two attributes
in battle. T he first is the serpent-ringed Aegis, the shield of
Zeus himself, which, when shook, wraps Mount Ida in clouds and
strikes men down with fear. T he second is the awful Gorgon’s head
on her breast. Feminist philosophers such as Kristine Downing and
Mary Daly would explain these attributes as honoring the shadow
side of woman and the dark sources of her power.7
Understanding the Emotions
Let us now examine the rage of Achilles through the paradigm of various disciplines and see whether their insights are helpful:
Greek philosophy; Freudian psychology; existential philosophy;
Christian dogmatism; and, mediation theory.
The ancient Greek view of the soul holds that the soul is divided
into reason (nous), appetite (epithymia), and spirit (thymos).
“Thymos” to the Greeks was “spiritedness,” where pride, a need
for recognition, and courage resided. W hen this part of the soul
was not satisfied, it reacted with “spirited” emotions, such as
shame and rage. Plato, for example, argues for this division of
the soul by describing examples of inner conflict: I desire to look
at a corpse (appetite) but I know that I should not (reason) and
I feel ashamed (spirit). T he similar, Aristotelian view holds that
the human soul is divided between rational and non-rational,
and the non-rational is further divided into parts obedient and
not obedient to reason.8
To the Greek philosophers, however, participating in an emotion
such as rage brought human beings closer to the world of
the gods. T o them, it was not the human beings who have their
passions, but rather the passions that have their human beings.
Further, rage belongs to a heroic character. I t is not simply deducible
from external provocations: “Achilles is wrathful just as the
North P ole is icy.”9
In the Iliad, Achilles’ rage was more of a force of nature than
an emotion. Even that early in our understanding of anger, a
question can be raised whether A chilles’ desecration of Hector’s
body was his losing control or taking control. S artre would favor
the latter interpretation, namely that rage is a strategy and has
a purpose. I n fact, by expressing rage, a party may be purposely
seeking to elevate him or herself into a position to be able to
pass judgment on the other party who has wronged him or her
and to have it both ways, that is, to place his or her claim before
the judge, while at the same time being the judge. T he substantive
disagreement between Sartre and the Greek philosophers is
whether the psyche is divided between controlling and controlled
elements. T he Greek philosophers saw appetites and emotions as
largely involuntary reactions, which ought to be controlled by the
exercise of reason. Sartre sees appetites and emotions as voluntary
actions, which are themselves forms of control. S artre denies the
distinction between voluntary and non-voluntary psychic elements.
Feeling ashamed about a desire I know I should not have is
not a battle between passive and active, chosen and un-chosen
elements of the soul, but a tension between equally voluntary,
equally intentional, yet distinct modes of consciousness. T ake
anger for example. Sartre’s thesis is that anger – like any mode
of consciousness – is a way of living and in fact, a way of choosing
one’s relation to the world. O ne does not “give in” to anger;
anger is chosen. However, to choose anger is not to reflectively
distance oneself from one’s anger and then embrace it after weighing
alternatives. T his would be to assume a split between the
rational and emotional sides of the soul. Disagreeing with the
Greek philosophers, who claim that choosing and directing are
actions unique to reason, Sartre would say that emotion chooses and directs. Reason does not stand back and choose my emotion;
emotion chooses to reveal the world.10
Psychological theory is in accord. Freud coined the term
“narcissism” as early as 1911 and four years later recognized the
aggressive impulse as a facet of narcissism. I t has come to be
understood in the field that Freud’s “aggression” is close to the
current concept of “narcissistic rage.” As Kohut wrote in the early
1970’s, this narcissistic rage is a reaction to the frustration of the
omnipotence of the grandiose self. T he integration and repair of
the damaged self through an individual’s capacity for empathy for
his offenders can cause a “shift” of the aggression produced by this
narcissistic rage. Just so does Homer recount A chilles’ transition
from narcissistic rage to a capacity for compassion and concern.11
Earliest Christian dogmatism considered anger something to
be restrained. P aul, in 2COR 12:20 and GAL 5:20, uses “thymos” in
the plural to designate outbursts of rage, correlating with infantile
or narcissistic rage. Note that the early Christian philosophers
much more frequently used “thymos” to connote rage, rather
than spiritedness, as did the Greek philosophers. GAL 5:19-21
includes this type of anger in a list of vices as “the works of the
flesh” along with fornication, impurity, licentiousness, idolatry,
sorcery, enmities, strife, jealousy, quarrels, dissensions, factions,
envy, drunkenness, and carousing.12 S t. Augustine (354 – 430 CE)defined rage as inherently aiming at revenge (iraappetitvindictam).
Pope Gregory I (c. 540 – 604 CE) included rage or wrath
in his list of seven deadly sins, along with lust, gluttony, greed,
sloth, envy and pride.
Confronting the Emotions
Now, what to do when confronted with the angry family law
litigant? How does one assuage the wrath of Achilles? I suggest
that Homer had it right and that the same martial arts techniques,
these attributes of the goddess Athena, which have matured over
a millennium in defending against physical aggression, provide
a method. I n fact, contemporary mediation theory specifically
adopts martial-arts terminology and attempts to utilize martial arts
techniques in the “principled negotiation” developed at the
Harvard Negotiation P roject.13 Such literature is replete with terms
such as “negotiation jujitsu,” “pushing back,” “side stepping,”
“deflecting,” “stepping aside,” “turn their strength to your ends,”
etc. Unfortunately, if a very brief intellectual discussion of an art
and discipline enabled one to use it effectively in the real world,
we lawyers would all become accomplished trial attorneys as soon
as we were handed our JD’s.
Be that as it may, I will describe some techniques from the
Japanese martial art of aikido that may be useful in dealing with the angry family law litigant.
Aikido is a fairly modern martial art invented in the 1930’s
by the martial genius Morihei Ueshiba, although many aikido
practitioners proclaim that aikido techniques derive from a much
earlier period. Ueshiba originally called his art aiki-budó. After
it was assimilated into the Butokukai in 1941, its name changed
to aikido.14 Despite its early roots, aikido is a modern martial art
because it was created after the M eiji period (1868 – 1912 CE)..
Further, the more one seeks to glorify Aikido’s roots, the less one
acknowledges Ueshiba’s greatness. S till further, from a mediation
perspective, it is far more useful to utilize techniques invented in
a comparably peaceful era when martial arts had evolved from a
Bujutsu to a B udo during the Tokugawa bakufu (1603 – 1868),
than to seek to utilize martial techniques designed for slaughter
during the Yoritomobakufu (1190 – 1199 CE) for principled negotiation.
There are great differences between the Bujutsu, or martial
arts, and the B udo, or martial ways. T he Bujutsu are combative
systems designed by and for warriors to promote self-protection
and group solidarity. T he B udo are spiritual systems, not necessarily
designed by warriors or for warriors, for self-protection of the
individual. I n any event, as aikido was invented in the 1930’s, it
is certainly not a classical Bujutsu(koryúbujutsu) and, by definition,
not a classical Budo (gendaibudo). I t is a modern B udo.15However, to consider aikido as a B udo, more spiritual system than
combative system, does not mean that its martial techniques,
and thus their facility to diffuse anger in both the physical and
psychological realm, are any less vital.
The spiritualism which pervades aikido is Buddhism, including
elements of discipline and paradigm-shifting techniques of
Zen Buddhism, rather than the elaborate ritualism of the Tendai
and Shingon sects.16
That said, aikido excels in “tai sabaki,” body-shifting; techniques
of entering, blending and moving off the line of attack to
diffuse resistance, resentment and anger, allowing the possibility of
reconciliation. Wonderful. W hat does this mean? T o be a successful
martial artist, one must have control of oneself. A successful
mediator must also have control of oneself. T he parties’ anger or
irrationality is the parties’, not yours. Aikido offers some practical
techniques to accomplish this. Perhaps the easiest is to control
your breathing. Try to breathe from your belly, not your upper
chest. Controlling your breathing causes a number of physical
and psychological changes in the body. I t also gives the mediator
something to do and succeed at, other than becoming fixated on
a party’s rage. Another Aikido technique for accomplishing this
is called “centering”. This is directing your consciousness to your
lower abdomen, the “seikatanden” or “hara,” an area called
the “one point.” O f course, you want to try to relax physically:
Drop your shoulders and soften them. Certainly no mammalian
posturing! N o staring contests, either!
First and foremost, you must remain professional, someone
worthy of respect. T he angry party will often seek to drag you down
to his or her level, or below. Do not cooperate. Very often, this is
enough. Consider how much energy it will take the raging party
to maintain his or her rage and how little energy it will take you
to remain calm, relaxed, breathing deeply and naturally.
If that doesn’t facilitate principled negotiation, then I would
recommend using a more dynamic aikido technique. Although
some mediators favor techniques such as “side stepping,” “deflecting,”
and “stepping aside,” I do not. Aikido with its Zen Buddhist
roots prefers engagement, to ducking, bobbing, and weaving.
Aikido has a technique called “irimi” or “to enter.” On the
physical plane this involves a strong forward movement toward the
attacker characterized by a powerful twist of the hips permitting
the aikidoist to enter the attacker’s space and leave the attacker
weakened with his “kuzushi” or balance broken. I am, of course,
discussing the use of martial art techniques for mediation, not
martial art techniques as a trial tactic, for which, of course, they
can be used.17
A Simplistic Ex ample
Now let me give you a very simplistic example of how the aikido
technique of “irimi” may be used. A very recently separated
husband and wife have sought your services. They have a lovely
10-year-old girl together. T he husband has left the wife to live
with his girlfriend in her apartment. B oth parties are fixated at the “negative intimacies phase” -- demonstrating for you insult
trading, struggles over power and control, and abusive anger.
You have screened for domestic violence and have determined
that mediation can proceed. The first issue presented is contact
between the girlfriend and the daughter. In a joint session, the
husband delights in telling you that the girlfriend is a far better
mother to the daughter than the wife ever was and he’ll decide
whose company his daughter will be in, not his wife. T he wife
responds that the girlfriend is a moral reprobate and shouldn’t be
permitted near barnyard animals. A nd there you have it.
Aikido, with its randori, defense against multiple attackers,
is sophisticated enough to understand well system dynamics. T o
this situation, you apply a technique that brings harmony to a
chaotic system. I n this simplistic example, I will deal with the
two “attackers” separately. Applying “irimi” to the husband, the
mediator enters his space, accepts the attack, applying centrifugal
force to “lead” rather than deflect the aggression. T he husband’s
statements are reframed. His high opinion of his girlfriend is
validated and his concerns are directed to specify what contact,
and how often, his girlfriend and his daughter shall enjoy.
The mediator similarly accepts the wife’s attack and enters
her space. S he is validated as the child’s mother and her concerns
about the girlfriend are acknowledged. Her attack on the character
of the girlfriend is led to the specific types of contact the girlfriend
and their child might share at this time; what would be tolerable
to their child?
Although this is a simplistic example, it should demonstrate
that aikido principles are in accord with contemporary mediation
theories, even those which do not presume to teach “negotiation
jujitsu.” Just as in the client-centered approach to mediation,
the use of aikido techniques places the parties’ fears, prejudices,
concerns, beliefs, and values as the focus of the process.18
Now, proceed with this mediation, and may the goddess Athena
bless you!
Endnotes
1. Opening lines of Homer’s Iliad, translated by Robert Fagles, 1990.
2. Hagedorn, J.& Caulfield, J., Real Lawyers Don’t Give In To Stress, Boston Bar
Journal, Vol. 37, No. 5; reprinted, Maine Lawyer’s Review, Vol. 1, No. 12, 1993.
3. Nelly, R., The Divorce Decision 9, 168 (1984).
4. Jaffe, P. G. &Geffner, R., Child Custody Disputes and Domestic Violence: Critical
Issues for Mental Health, Social Service, and Legal Professionals, CHILDREN EXPOSED
TO MARITAL VIOLENCE, 371, 374 (G. W. Holden, R. Geffner, & E. N. Jouriles, eds.,
1998).
5. Homer, The Iliad, Butler translation.
6. Meullner, L., The Anger of Achilles: Menis in Greek Ethic. Ithaca: Cornell University
Press, 1996.
7. Kinsley, D. R., The Goddess’ Mirror: Visions of the Divine from East and West,
State University of New York Press, Albany, 1989, pp. 139-164.
8. See Book IV of the Republic (Cambridge: Hackett, 1992.)
9. Wenning, M., The Return of Rage, Parrhesia, No. 8, pp. 89-99, 2009.
10. See generally The Emotions: Outlines of a Theory (New York: Citadel, 1948);
See also Sartre’s Ethics of Engagement: Authenticity and Civil Virtue, T. Storm Heter
(Continuum International Publishing Group, London, 2006).
11. Hyphantis et al, Narcissistic Rage: The Achilles’ heel of the patient with chronic
physical illness, publisher and licensee Dove Medical Press Ltd., 2009.
12. Kelhoffer, J. Suppressing Anger in Early Christianity: Examples from the Pauline
Tradition, Greek, Roman and Byzantine Studies 47 (2007) pp. 310, 311, and 320.
13. Fisher, R. &Ury, W., Getting To Yes Negotiating Agreement Without Giving In,
Penguin Books Ltd., New York, New York, 1981.
14. Ueshiba, M., Budo Teachings of the Founder of Aikido, Kodansha International,
Tokyo, 1991, pp. 16-18
15. Draeger, D. F., Classical Bujutsu, Weatherhill, New York and Tokyo, 1973, pp.
11-32; Draeger, D. F., Classical Budo, Weatherhill, New York and Tokyo, 1973, pp.
11-40.
16. Caulfield, J., Book Review of King’s Zen And The Way Of The Sword, Aikido
Today Magazine, Vol. 9, No. 1.
17. Caulfield, Aikido and the Trial Attorney, Aikido World, Volume 9, No. 2; reprinted
New England Martial Arts, Volume 1, No. 2.
18. McKnight and Erickson, Mediating Divorce A Step-by-Step Manual, Jossey-Bass,
1999.